ARGUMENTS ABOUT VALUES--HANDOUT I) Supporting criteria with a specific audience in mind Generally speaking, you will not have to defend any criteria your audience is likely to share; for example, if you are claiming that your friend is a "good student" you would probably not have to defend the criteria for a "good student" to that friend. But if your audience does not accept your criteria of evaluation to begin with, you need to determine ways by which you can support your criteria. While there are four methods for supporting criteria for a specific audience, i.e., authority, consequences, comparison, and values, we will be focusing only on values. Arguments premised on "values" are generally held (although this point is disputable) to be different from arguments based on "facts" as they do not appeal to a universal audience as would arguments based on "fact". Arguments with regard to values means an admission that a belief in an ideal, person or object may help support a particular action, but the success of this appeal may not be binding to everyone, but rather only to a specific audience. For example, while an argument based on the fact of gravity may appeal to a universal audience, an argument based on values about writing and specific definitions of literacy may only appeal to a limited group of people. If you can show that your standard of evaluation falls under one of your audience's basic assumptions about what has value then you have supported your criteria, at least for that audience. The following example illustrates an argument based on values with limited audience appeal. The novelist John Gardner evaluates much modern fiction as "trivial and corrupt." He claimed as his criterion for that evaluation that fiction should be a moral art. How could he back up that criterion, one with which many modern novelists and readers disagree? He could place that criterion under one of our basic assumptions by appealing to the self-evident goodness of what is moral. Moral is another word for choosing the good and repressing the bad and if we argue that trying to live according to this policy is admirable in life, shouldn't it also be admirable in fiction? Young and Sullivan's article, "Why Write", provides another illustration of criteria supported by values designed to address a specific audience, What these arguments share [Rohman, Progoff, Britton, and Olson] is the idea that writing enables us to think in ways that are otherwise improbable , or difficult, or even impossible. (Young and Sullivan, p. 216) The criterion used here for defending the value of writing is based on certain values concerning the type of thinking which writing engenders. While this argument may be readily accepted by some members of a literate community, it may not be accepted by members of an oral culture who believe that oral discourse enables equally as valuable cognitive abilities. Or it may not be accepted by people who find writing to be a difficult, and even a counterproductive task, and who rely on other means of expression and communication. II) Weighting values: ethical argument Consider the following case in terms of the ethical evaluation involved in making a decision: Is it right for a community and school board to allow the reading of the Bible (if such a decision is supported by a majority vote) while our educational system is supposed to maintain a separation of church and state? In this situation the issue is not "right action" versus "wrong action", but rather the issue at hand concerns several positive values which are in conflict, education, majority rule and religious freedom. A decision about a case such as this would involve weighting one value over another. Ethical argument involve making such very fine discriminations, ordering values in a hierarchy to make possible the judgment of action. In an ethical argument, you and your audience might agree on certain values, but not necessarily order those values the same way. Your job in argument is to weight one value, the one that will become the critical criterion of judgment, above the other. Evaluating values in this way is a matter of stance, that faced with a choice, being well educated is more important than being wealthy (or vice versa). No matter what you are evaluating, from an object to a value itself, most of the time weighting will be the crucial issue with your audience. People are likely to agree about the relevance of a set of criteria but disagree about which is most important in a given situation. I) Arguments about premises When a speaker/writer presents the premises (i.e., the starting point of the argument) upon which he/she builds an argument, he/she is assuming (or counting on) the audience's acceptance of that premise. However, the audience may not always accept this premise: they do not adhere to what the speaker/writer presents as being generally accepted; they may see this premise as one-sided; they may not accept the way in which the premise was presented. As such, it is important in building your argument to carefully consider the question of what sort of agreements can serve as effective premises. While not all encompassing, we will look at types of objects of agreement that play different roles in the arguing process. These types of objects of agreement fall into 2 classes: 1) real: facts, truths, and presumptions 2) preferable: values, hierarchies, and, in general, lines of argument concerning what is preferable in a given situation Even though the 2 classes separate values from facts and truths, it is important to recognize that in many ways this classification is a false one as arguments about values almost always enter a debate as some stage of an argument. For example, the reasoning processes used in the hard sciences ( a discipline generally held to present "facts" and "truths" which are removed from any form of subjective value judgment) are generally confined to the beginning of the formulation of the concepts and rules that makeup the framework which the discipline operates within. In other words, information which is considered to be factual and truthful is, even in the hard sciences, relative to the norms and values upon which the discipline is based. Relatedly, when a writer/speaker presents information which he/she claims to be a "fact" or to be "true", the reasoning or justification supporting this claim must also be presented. And the reader/hearer needs to become skilled in questioning someone's presentation and assumptions underlying their claims of presenting facts. Furthermore, the status of statements evolve: over time values, through various processes may become accepted as facts and/or truths, just as facts and truths may be understood to be value judgments.